Sunday, 2 December 2012


3. Some Thoughts on the Death of Neil Armstrong

Like many people of my age, I was brought up with an awareness of the Apollo Space Program. Some of my earliest memories are of my mother coming upstairs in the middle of the night and bringing my down to the den where my parents and I would watch, on our black and white TV, some essential manoeuvre prior to the actual moon shot—a trial run of the lunar lander in earth orbit, a there-and-back again trip to orbit the moon itself. I'm told that at the age of two I could describe, in basic terms, the workings of a Saturn V rocket, and I remember quite clearly not only most of the lift-offs and splash downs from the Apollo age, but also the live broadcast of Commander Armstrong's historic first steps on another world. In fact, this is one of the first memories to which I can fix an exact time.

These memories were formative, as they were for many other children of my generation and slightly older, but I do not intend here to plunge into nostalgia. Rather, I'd like to think about the memories themselves—the images—and the ways in which I thought about them then as opposed to the ways in which I have since come to consider them. As a kid, when I looked at a rocket, I saw a space ship, and when I looked at an astronaut, I saw what I wanted to be: a person who flew in space ships. The two were distinct entities: one was a human being, and the other was really cool stuff. I think this is still the general perception, but it becomes incomplete the moment we wonder where the identity “astronaut” actually resides.

Even taking out the rocket for the moment and just looking at the image below, taken by Buzz Aldrin with a movie camera from the hatch of the lunar module, the problems in fixing a location to an identity become clear. The image shows Armstrong in his space suit, walking on the moon's surface, into the shadow of the lander. But it would be inaccurate to say that the figure walking on the moon exclusively Armstrong as, without the suit providing him with oxygen and preventing him from exploding in the vacuum, it would not be possible to walk there. That is, the identity “astronaut” only makes sense in this case if the suit is included in the understanding of the term. Armstrong is, to use a term coined by Clynes and Kline and cited int he first entry of this blog, a “self sustaining man-machine system,” or in other words a cyborg.



Photo: Mail Online, Sept. 7, 2012: (URL provided below*)

This is not to take away from the achievements of any person who has participated in any space programme. The skill, training, intelligence, and courage needed to get to where Armstrong stands in this image were exemplary and demand respect. Nor do I mean to make the figure seem alien to the rest of humanity: if offered a chance to travel into space, my first and unconditional response would hopefully be “Borg me up.” I do not think I'd be alone in such a reaction. It is worth considering, however, that the identities we enact do not reside exclusively in our biological selves.

The question of the identity “astronaut” is further complicated when we pull back a little and realize that the actual system that made these particular enactments possible consisted of the lunar lander itself, and two astronaut-cyborgs, each composed of one human body and one space suit, in neither of which this identity could be said to reside in isolation. Orbiting above the moon's surface was the command module, also integral to the system, piloted by yet another astronaut-cyborg, in this case Michael Collins.

So now we have at least three basic components to the identity in question: ship, suit, and human being, each insufficient in itself. Yet in order to function, the command module-Collins unit had to rely on its radio link to mission control in Houston, and the room full of computers and technicians that operated constantly for the duration of the mission. Without all of these components, there would be no boot prints on the moon. And if we broaden the context a little more, we see the makers of the equipment itself—the scientists and technicians who designed the ICBMs on which the Saturn V and all other launch vehicles are based, the computer programmers, the dietary experts, and the trainers, the teachers, and professors who taught not just the astronauts but also everyone else who played a responsible role. In short, we see virtually the entire social structure of the United States. So the question arises: who, exactly, went to the moon?

The easy answer is Armstrong, Aldrin, and Collins. This is not a bad answer as far as it goes as it has the obvious virtue of being clearly and demonstrably true. Another possibility, though, lies in the popular usage in the U.S., that “we” went to the Moon. From a cyborg point of view, this position is not mere nationalism or jingoism, but is in fact quite accurate. The space programme in the Apollo age marked a pinnacle of American national achievement, and in this sense, the footprints in the lunar dust really are the prints of an entire culture—a single, though often troubled, identity, of which the three men in the capsule were simply the leading edge.

Thursday, 21 June 2012


2. Replicants and Little Purple Berries: John Locke vs. the Weeds in my Grandparents' Backyard

One Sunday in late summer when I was almost five, our family went to my grandparents' house for dinner. It was a beautiful evening, so my two-year-old sister and I went out into the backyard to play while the grownups sat inside and smoked—all grownups, at that time, smoked. Anyway, the backyard was getting a little wild as the energy that used to keep it tidy was no longer present in the house. Along one side, following the line of the old wire fence, was a garden, or what had once been a garden, now overgrown with weeds. Weeds are fun when you're almost five, especially when some of the plants have little purple berries.

I know what you're thinking, and yes, my parents had warned me repeatedly about not eating berries I couldn't identify. And yes, I had understood these warnings, for instance when my mum had sat me on her lap and told me quite tearfully how horrible my death would be for her and my dad. So when I picked the first berry and put it in my mouth, I had a pretty good idea that I was doing something wrong and dangerous, or least very much against the rules. Probably, that's why they tasted so sweet, or at least I like to think so, and probably, it's why I ate so damned many of them. My sister seemed to enjoy them as well, at least the few that she had time to eat before the backdoor opened and my mother came running out.

Oh my God,” she said. “How many of these did she eat?”

Lots,” I replied, my own hands and mouth momentarily empty. Or at least that's how I remember it now, though at times I remember the answer as being “not many.”

No matter.

Have you had any?” she asked next.

No,” I replied. This one, I remember precisely.

Oh my God,” she may have said again before calling into the house: “Ron! Joanne's been eating purple nightshade.”1

So that evening, rather than gathering around Grandma Wilkie's excellent Yorkshire pudding and her typically overcooked roast beef, we went first to the hospital where the physician gave my sister some medicine, and then home where she spent much of the night throwing up into a bowl. Or at least I think she did. Personally, I slept quite well.

Two years later, I was lying in bed wide awake. It was dark, and my mind was wandering. Random voices were drifting into my awareness from downstairs where my parents were entertaining company. Maybe I'd just woken up from a doze. Maybe I'd been staring at the ceiling for a couple of hours. I don't know. What I do know is that at some point, my mind wandered back to my grandparents' backyard and my thus-far unspoken poison berry feast. As I lay there, drifting in the grown-up voices and second-hand smoke seeping under my bedroom door, a line of thought formed in my head:

I ate a lot of poison berries.
Poison berries can kill you.
Maybe they killed me.
What if I'm dead?
But if I'm dead, how can I be here?
What if I'm not really here, but only think I am?
What if I died, and my parents replaced me with a robot?
What if I'm really a robot who only thinks its me?
I don't want to be a robot.
How can I be sure I'm not?
Maybe I should ask Mum and Dad.

At this point I got out of bed and headed down the stairs, settling in my favourite spot three steps from the bottom, around the corner from the living room. The nearness of voices made me feel more connected, and for a few minutes, this helped. The relief didn't last, though, and eventually I went to the bottom of the stairs and stepped around the corner. The conversation stopped, and after one look at my face, my mother called me over to her seat at the end of the couch. I curled up on her lap, and she asked me what was the matter:

Remember when Joanne ate all those poison berries?”
Yes.”
I ate some, too.”
Yes?”
I ate more than her.”
OK?”
So did I die? Did you replace me with a robot? Mummy, am I a robot?”

This took Mum off guard. I recall her staring at me for a minute, maybe trying not to laugh or maybe just wondering how to respond. After a moment during which my parents' guests waited quietly, she hugged me close.

No, Sweetie,” she said. “You're not a robot.”
Do you promise?”
I promise.”

And that was that. For the next few decades, I had an amusing story about my childhood imagination. Then, a few months ago, I showed the movie Blade Runner (1982) to the class in Human Nature and Technology that I co-teach with Dr. Andrew Moore. This movie features artificial beings, called replicants, outwardly indistinguishable from humans, capable of passing themselves off a homo sapiens unless subjected to a psychological examination known as the Voight-Kampff test. The test confronts suspected replicants with emotionally charged questions and then assesses their responses as a measure of their humanity or non-humanity. As a means to prevent these artificial creatures from posing a serious threat to human beings, they have been banned from the surface of the planet, and are used instead as soldiers and workers in various industries and services off-world. As a further safeguard, the Tyrell Corporation, which manufactures them, has set a four-year limit to their lifespans. As a final means of control—a way of mitigating the violent emotions that might result from such a bleak outlook—later-model replicants are implanted with memories. In the case of Rachael, the latest model, with an indeterminate lifespan and no awareness of her own artificiality, the memories are borrowed from the niece of her designer, Dr. Eldon Tyrell, founder and CEO of the Tyrell Corporation. In addition to these transplanted memories, Rachael has a collection of photographs, also of Tyrell's niece, which she believes to have been taken in her own non-existent youth. The unsettling part—rather, one of the unsettling parts, as the movie abounds in these—occurs when Rick Deckard, the film's titular blade runner (replicant killer), overhears her playing the piano. At this point in the film, Rachael has become aware of her own artificiality and thus knows that she never actually took piano lessons. And yet, she remembers having taken them, and demonstrably possesses the skill that the lessons she never had, have in fact imparted. Rachael's character, then, exemplifies a continuity between the real memories of Tyrell's nameless niece and her own real capacities.

So if we want to view Rachael as a person, and her demonstrations of both emotional and rational experience suggest quite strongly that we should, how exactly do we think of her? What are the boundaries of this potential person? And for that matter, what do we even mean by “person”? This is a word often taken for granted, as in conversation at least, its meaning seems self-evident: a human being. But this is not the only or even the best possible definition, as the ubiquity, at least in Western jurisprudence, of the insanity defence against a criminal charge attests: the assertion that, at a given time and for reasons of mental debility, the accused is not responsible for the crimes that his or her body committed, i.e. the person of the defendant and the person who did the actions in question are functionally distinct, notwithstanding the fact that they share one body.

But if being human is not sufficient for personhood, what is? I'm reminded of a passage from John Locke's Essay Concerning Human Understanding (1690), which I'll quote at length. Locke defines the term “person” as follows:

a thinking intelligent being, that has reason and reflection, and can consider itself as itself, the same thinking thing, in different times and places; which it does only by that consciousness which is inseparable from thinking. ... Thus is it always as to our present sensations and perceptions: and by this every one is to himself that which he calls SELF:—it not being considered, in this case, whether the same self be continued in the same or divers substances. For, since consciousness always accompanies thinking, and it is that which makes every one to be what he calls self, and thereby distinguishes himself from all other thinking things, in this alone consists personal identity, i.e. the sameness of a rational being: and as far as consciousness can be extended backwards to any past action or thought, so far reaches the identity of that person. (John Locke. Essay Concerning Human Understanding. II xxvii 11)

Here, Locke takes rationality, self-awareness, and continuity of memory as necessary and sufficient conditions for personhood. Interestingly, Locke's definition leaves open the possibility that personhood need not be materially continuous. By this definition it is at least theoretically possible, given reason, self-awareness, and memory, for a person to begin existence in one material form and then continue it in another.

When applied to Blade Runner, Locke's definition offers some interesting possibilities. As Rachael remembers taking the piano lessons for which her body was never present, and as the effect of those lessons is her actual ability to make music, the film suggests a continuity of memory between Tyrell's human niece and the non-human construct. Rachael's self-awareness is also telling, particularly in her conversation with Deckard after saving his life by shooting fellow replicant Leon. Rachael is visibly upset after the killing:

Deckard: Shakes? Me too.
Rachael: What?
Deckard: I get 'em bad, It's part of the business.
Rachael: I'm not in the business. I am the business.

Her rationality by this point has also been clearly established, particularly during the Voight-Kampff test, which Deckard administers on their first meeting, unaware at first that she is not human. Tyrell introduces her to Deckard by stating, “I want to see it work on a person. I want to see a negative before I provide you with a positive.” His use of “person” draws attention to the discrepancy between his and Deckard's understandings of what this word might mean, and Rachael's responses are so close to what Deckard, previously identified as the best of all blade runners, would expect from a human being, that it takes him over a hundred questions—more than triple his own average—to identify her nature. She functions, in other words, as a rational and emotionally stable human would be expected to function.

So Rachael the replicant possesses reason and self-awareness, and has a continuity of memory stretching back to a specific human childhood that her body never had. She thus is a person who spans not only two bodies but also two orders of being—one biological and one technological. There is a continuity of experience and identity between these two beings, who merge to form one identifiable and functional self. The situation is further complicated by the fact that Tyrell's niece may still be alive—the film provides no information on this question—and so may also constitute a self composed largely of the memories she shares with Rachael. That is, a single set of lived experiences has probably given rise to two distinct persons, both of whom have valid claims for seeing the associated memories as their own. If such were not the case, the replicant would not be able to play the piano.

So what does any of this have to do with the berries in my grandparents' garden? The short answer is that it completely invalidates the fears of my seven-year-old self. Consider, for example, the following thought experiment:

Imagine two parallel universes. In the first, events played out as I've described, but in the second, I died—given the number of berries I ate, quite frankly, I should have—and was replaced, unbeknownst to my parents and other relations, by a robot in all ways indistinguishable from my biological self. This robot was now wearing my clothes and honestly believed that it was me, and the lives of these two hypothetical Rodgers had proceeded along identical paths. Allowing for the existence of both of these universes, it would be impossible at any given moment to know which one I was actually living in. Given the impossibility of knowing, and given the identity of experience, the question of which being is the biological version and which the technological version becomes functionally meaningless.

From the point if view of personhood, the question is just not worth asking. On the other hand—sticking with the thought experiment—the psychological anxiety experienced by both Rodgers would have to be seen as equally real: their physical make-up is identical, after all, and the sites of anxiety in each case would necessarily be their brains. Thus, the anxiety of the being, rather than the substance of the being, becomes a central consideration: the presence or absence of suffering is more important than either the physical stuff or the particular origins of the sufferer. To broaden the spectrum a little further, consider this parting thought: if the lived experience is real, the reality of the being who embodies the experience is a given, it being irrational to assert that an unreal being can have a real experience. Where reason, self-awareness, and continuity of memory exist, therefore, so does the the necessity of full inclusion in the moral community of persons.

Mummy, am I a robot?”
Mummy, am I a simulation?”
Mummy, am I a clone?”
“I have no idea, Sweetie, and it doesn't matter anyway.”

Pleasant dreams.



1 The Poison Garden Website (http://www.thepoisongarden.co.uk/atoz/atropa_belladonna.htm) offers the following comments on the toxicity of purple nightshade:
Symptoms may be slow to appear but last for several days. They include dryness in the mouth, thirst, difficulty in swallowing and speaking, blurred vision from the dilated pupils, vomiting, excessive stimulation of the heart, drowsiness, slurred speech, hallucinations, confusion, disorientation, delirium, and agitation. Coma and convulsions often precede death.
There is disagreement over what constitutes a fatal amount with cases cited of a small child eating half a berry and dying alongside a nine year old Danish boy who, in the 1990s, ate between twenty and twenty five berries and survived.”

Sunday, 26 February 2012

1. Some of my Best Friends are Cyborgs

Why write a blog about cyborgs?


There are many ways I could answer that question. I might give a few definitions—maybe the original definition proposed by Clynes and Kline in 1960, “self-sustaining man-machine systems” (30), a more recent one by Hess, “any identity between machine and human or any conflation of the machine/human boundary” (373) or any other workable formulation. Haraway has a good one in Primate Visions: “the figure born of the interface of automaton and autonomy” that exists “when two kinds of boundaries are simultaneously problematic: 1) that between animals (or other organisms) and humans, and 2) that between self-controlled, self-governing machines (automatons) and organisms, especially humans (models of autonomy).” What all of these definitions have in common is the idea of the interface between the organic and the technological, and their configuration into a single system. So that's a cyborg.

Very nice, but why write about them?

A few obvious reasons come to mind. They're fun, especially in a sexy high-tech science-fictiony sort of way. We have cyborgs in comic books, cyborgs in novels, cyborgs in movies, cyborgs on TV shows, cyborgs in video games. They are a part of our popular consciousness—part of the things we make so that we can think more clearly about ourselves. They address our fears and uncertainties on the one hand, and our dreams and desires on the other. Is modern life undermining our humanity? Are we becoming more machine-like as our machines give us increasing mastery, or the illusion of mastery, over our physical environments? But wouldn't it be nice to be able to access all that information out there—all that power—by letting it stream into our brains as fast as we want at the times of our choosing? And seriously ... At least once, haven't you wanted a laser canon mounted to your arm? If you haven't before, you probably do now.

We are afraid of becoming cyborgs; we want to become cyborgs.

Relax: you're already a cyborg.

To many of you, I realize, this argument will be familiar, so I will not dwell on it at length. For a more complete version of my own take on the question, see my article in Fragments (forthcoming as of this writing: URL http://quod.lib.umich.edu/f/frag/). Or for simplicity's sake, you might consider the oft-cited assertion of Gray, Mentor, and Figueroa-Sarriera in their introduction to the Cyborg Handbook: “Anyone with an artificial organ, limb or supplement (like a pacemaker), anyone reprogrammed to resist disease (immunized) or drugged to think/behave/feel better (psychopharmacology) is technically a cyborg” (2-3). That is, if your body has been modified to either enable or improve its functioning even in your day-to-day environment, you are no longer a purely biological entity; you are a hybrid of biology and technology. Alternately, we might employ N. Katherine Hayles’ category of the metaphoric cyborg, a category she sees as “including the computer keyboarder joined in a cybernetic circuit with the screen, the neurosurgeon guided by fiber optic microscopy during an operation” (322), or in other words anyone who temporarily links with technology to engage in an activity that would otherwise be difficult or impossible. Or if you would prefer, we might consider the argument in Andy Clark's Natural Born Cyborgs. Clark understands cyborgs as “human-technology symbionts: thinking and reasoning systems whose minds and selves are spread across biological brain and non-biological circuitry” (3); sees the mind as an intelligence distributed across both biological and non-biological media (4) such as spoken language, print, and electronic files; and argues that “what blinds us tour own increasingly cyborg nature is an ancient western prejudice—the tendency to think of the mind as so deeply special as to be distinct from the rest of the natural order” (26). In other words, take any notions of purity that you ever cherished—biological, racial, cultural—and move them to your internal recycle bin.

An objection that one might raise to this position is that the term cyborg becomes so watered down as to be virtually meaningless. The objection is reasonable and by no means hypothetical: I've encountered it from both students and senior colleagues. My response is that the labelling of a broad range of identities as cyborgs is not so much a dilution of the concept cyborg as it is a reconsideration of the category person. I am interested in exploring the contribution of technological elements to personal identity, or more accurately to personhood, remaining open to the possibility that these elements are not merely things used by a self but rather are modular components of a self. Identity in other words may be modular, and I am interested in thinking about how the modules fit together.

But my purpose in this blog is not to prove that we are all cyborgs. Rather, it is to consider, in a format different from the world of academic conferences and journals on the one hand and from the classroom on the other hand, what it means to be a cyborg. This is the main question I want to explore in these meditations, and in doing so, I intend to range across a fairly heterogeneous array of material, including but not limited to science and technology studies, Western and Eastern philosophy, literature, mythology, pop culture, and personal reflection. Some posts will be more or less academic; others may look like diary entries; some will be a hybrid of the two. There is nothing like a concrete agenda as the blog will not merely be a record of thought so much as a vehicle for it. That's a fancy way of saying that I'm making this up as I go. So whoever you are who find this, I hope you stick around for a while. I hope you share some of your own thoughts. And I hope you enjoy it.

Works Cited

Clark, Andy. Natural Born Cyborgs: Minds, Technologies, and the Future of Human Intelligence. Oxford. Oxford U.P., 2003.

Clynes, Manfred E. and Nathan S. Kline. “Cyborgs and Space.” The Cyborg Handbook. Ed. Chris Hables Gray. New York and London: Routledge, 1995. 29-34. Rpt. from Astronautics (Sept. 1960): 26-27, 74-75.

Gray, Chris Hables, Steven Mentor, and Heidi J. Figueroa-Sarriera. “Cyborgology: Constructing the Knowledge of Cybernetic Organisms.” The Cyborg Handbook. Ed. Chris Hables Gray. New York and London: Routledge, 1995. 1-14.

Haraway, Donna. Primate Visions: Gender, Race, and Nature in the World of Modern Science. New York and London: Routledge, 1989.

Hayles, N. Katherine. “The Life Cycle of Cyborgs: Writing the Posthuman.” The Cyborg Handbook. Ed. Chris Hables Gray. New York and London: Routledge, 1995. 321-35. Rpt. from A Question of Identity. Ed. Marina Benjamin. Rutgers U P, 1993.

Hess, David J. “On Low-Tech Cyborgs.” The Cyborg Handbook. Ed. Chris Hables Gray. New York and London: Routledge, 1995. 371-77.

Wilkie, Rodger. “Epic Hero as Cyborg: An Experiment in Interpreting Pre-Modern Heroic Narrative,” Fragments 2 (2012). http://quod.lib.umich.edu/f/frag.